# Entanglement Entanglement is a [mysterious](https://www.informationphilosopher.com/freedom/mysteries.html) quantum phenomenon that is widely, but mistakenly, described as capable of transmitting information over vast distances faster than the speed of light. It has proved very popular with science writers, philosophers of science, and many scientists who hope to use the mystery to deny some of the basic concepts underlying quantum physics. Beyond this claim, which violates the principle of relativity, is the claim that entanglement "connects" every particle in the universe with every other particle, implying a "holistic" or "implicate" order in the universe, which is popular with "new age" thinkers and other mystics who see in it [pan-psychism](https://www.informationphilosopher.com/mind/panpsychism/), or "cosmic consciousness," or at a minimum "telepathic powers" between entangled minds. Entanglement depends on two quantum properties that are thought to be impossible in "classical" physics. One is called _[nonlocality](https://www.informationphilosopher.com/problems/nonlocality/)_. We shall argue that [Albert Einstein](https://www.informationphilosopher.com/solutions/scientists/einstein/) first caught a glimpse of nonlocality as early as his photoelectric effect paper, published in June of 1905, when he questioned how a continuous light wave spread out in space could instantly collapse all its energy to become localized in the discrete quantum of energy needed to eject an electron. We call this "collapse" because it was the first insight into what the founders of quantum mechanics over twenty years later would call the "[collapse of the wave function](https://www.informationphilosopher.com/quantum/collapse/)." At this early time, Einstein already said explicitly that the instantaneous relocation of the light wave appeared to violate his brand new relativity principle, published in September of that "miracle year." Einstein again discussed the fundamental connection between a particle and its wave nature in 1909, when he said that physics in the future will require a "fusion" of the [wave and particle](https://www.informationphilosopher.com/introduction/physics/wave-particle_duality.html) pictures. Einstein saw the _continuous_ light wave as a "ghost field" or "guiding field" somehow determining the probabilities of locating the _discrete_ light quanta. That was years before [Louis de Broglie](https://www.informationphilosopher.com/solutions/scientists/debroglie/) argued that material particles have associated "pilot waves" (1924), leading [Erwin Schrödinger](https://www.informationphilosopher.com/solutions/scientists/schrodinger/) to develop his wave function ψ and his wave mechanics (1926). Einstein made a clear public statement about the connection between the wave function and the photon particle twenty-two years after his photoelectric effect paper, at the 1927 Solvay conference on "Electrons and Photons." > |ψ|2 expresses the probability that there exists at the point considered a particular particle of the cloud, for example at a given point on the screen. > > > (_Quantum Theory at the Crossroads: Reconsidering the 1927 Solvay Conference_, G. Bacciagaluppi and A. Valentini, 2009. pp.440-442) Einstein's remarks were misunderstood but well reported by [Niels Bohr](https://www.informationphilosopher.com/solutions/scientists/bohr/). These concerns of Einstein's about nonlocality were ignored by most physicists until 1935 and the appearance of the famous [Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen](https://www.informationphilosopher.com/solutions/experiments/EPR/) paper, in which Einstein feared there was some kind of "spooky action-at-a-distance." The other "impossible" quantum property is _[nonseparability](https://www.informationphilosopher.com/problems/nonseparability/)_, which Einstein also was first to see, even as he attacked the idea. Note that this negative reaction was just as Einstein had reacted to his unwelcome discovery of [indeterminism](https://www.informationphilosopher.com/problems/entanglement/'freedom/indeterminism.html) in 1916, when he attacked the appearance of [chance](https://www.informationphilosopher.com/chance/) (_Zufall_) in the direction of emitted photons as a "weakness in the theory." Both ontological chance and the "holistic" [nonseparability](https://www.informationphilosopher.com/problems/nonseparability/) of particles described by a single wave function were first seen by Einstein long before they became standard elements in quantum mechanics. In 1933 Einstein suggested we can [know](https://www.informationphilosopher.com/knowledge/) the position or the momentum of one particle simply by measuring the position or momentum of another particle with which it had interacted in the past. Since it requires no interaction between the particles, we can call this "knowledge-at-a-distance." It depends only on the classical laws of motion and especially the conservation laws for energy, linear momentum, and angular momentum. In the 1935 EPR paper Einstein extended nonlocality beyond the relation between a light-quantum particle and its "wave function." Back in 1926 [Erwin Schrödinger](https://www.informationphilosopher.com/solutions/scientists/schrodinger/) invented the "wave function" Ψ as the solution to his "wave equation." In 1927 [Max Born](https://www.informationphilosopher.com/solutions/scientists/born/) had identified Ψ2 as the probability of finding a quantum particle somewhere, following a suggestion of Einstein in the early 1920's. Before 1933 the great difficulty was understanding the relationship between a single particle and its wave function Ψ. What Einstein did now was a thought experiment about _two particles_ and their two-particle wave function Ψ12. It turned out that the two-particle wave function can not be separated into the product of two single-particle wave functions Ψ1 and Ψ2. Nonlocality was now extended by Einstein from a light particle and its light wave, to perfect "correlations" between one material particle and another with which it had interacted in the past. In his response to the EPR paper, Schrödinger called particles with such correlated properties "entangled" and he told Einstein about the necessary conditions under which Ψ12 could be "separated" into Ψ1 and Ψ2. After separation, they would be [disentangled](https://www.informationphilosopher.com/quantum/disentanglement/) and [decohered](https://www.informationphilosopher.com/quantum/decoherence/). ## Einstein's Discovery of [Nonlocality](https://www.informationphilosopher.com/problems/entanglement/%3Ca%20href=) and [Nonseparability](https://www.informationphilosopher.com/problems/entanglement/%3Ca%20href=) Einstein was the first to see _nonlocal_ behavior in quantum phenomena. He may have seen it as early as 1905 in the photoelectric effect, the same year he published his special theory of relativity. But it was perfectly clear to him 22 years later (ten years after his general theory of relativity and his explanation of how quanta of light are _randomly_ emitted and absorbed by atoms), when he described nonlocality with a diagram on the blackboard at an international conference of physicists in Belgium in 1927 at the fifth Solvay conference. In his contribution to the 1949 [Schilpp memorial volume](http://www.amazon.com/Albert-Einstein-Philosopher-Scientist-Library-Philosophers/dp/0875482864) on Einstein, [Niels Bohr](https://www.informationphilosopher.com/solutions/scientists/bohr/) gave us a picture of what Einstein drew on that blackboard. > At the general discussion in [Como](https://www.informationphilosopher.com/solutions/scientists/bohr/quantum_postulate.html), we all missed the presence of Einstein, but soon after, in October 1927, I had the opportunity to meet him in Brussels at the Fifth Physical Conference of the Solvay Institute, which was devoted to the theme "Electrons and Photons."  > > Note that they wanted Einstein's reaction to their work, but actually took little interest in Einstein's concern about the _nonlocal_ implications of quantum mechanics. > > At the Solvay meetings, Einstein had from their beginning been a most prominent figure, and several of us came to the conference with great anticipations to learn his reaction to the latest stage of the development which, to our view, went far in clarifying the problems which he had himself from the outset elicited so ingeniously. During the discussions, where the whole subject was reviewed by contributions from many sides and where also the arguments mentioned in the preceding pages were again presented, Einstein expressed, however, a deep concern over the extent to which a causal account in space and time was abandoned in quantum mechanics. > > To illustrate his attitude, Einstein referred at one of the sessions to the simple example, illustrated by Fig. 1, of a particle (electron or photon) penetrating through a hole or a narrow slit in a diaphragm placed at some distance before a photographic plate. > > ![photon passes through a slit](https://www.informationphilosopher.com/solutions/scientists/bohr/images/Bohr-Einstein-1.jpg) > > On account of the diffraction of the wave connected with the motion of the particle and indicated in the figure by the thin lines, it is under such conditions not possible to predict with certainty at what point the electron will arrive at the photographic plate, but only to calculate the probability that, in an experiment, the electron will be found within any given region of the plate. > > The "nonlocal" effect at point (B) is just the probability of an electron being found at point (B) going to zero instantly (as if an "action-at-a-distance") the moment an electron is found at point A > > The apparent difficulty, in this description, which Einstein felt so acutely, is the fact that, if in the experiment the electron is recorded at one point A of the plate, then it is out of the question of ever observing an effect of this electron at another point (B), although the laws of ordinary wave propagation offer no room for a correlation between two such events. > > > ("Discussion with Einstein," by Niels Bohr, _Albert Einstein, Philosopher-Scientist_, P. A. Schilpp, 1949. pp.211-213) Bohr is telling us that in 1927 Einstein saw instantaneous "correlations" of events widely separated ("as if actions-at-a-distance"), which exactly describes today's perfect "nonlocal" correlations of widely separated entangled particles. Later. in 1935, Einstein, [Boris Podolsky](http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Boris_Podolsky), and [Nathan Rosen](http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Nathan_Rosen) proposed a [thought experiment (known by their initials as EPR)](https://www.informationphilosopher.com/solutions/experiments/EPR/) to exhibit internal contradictions in the new quantum physics. They hoped to show that quantum theory could not describe certain intuitive "elements of reality" and thus was either _incomplete_ or, as they might have hoped, demonstrably incorrect. Einstein and his colleagues [Erwin Schrödinger](https://www.informationphilosopher.com/solutions/scientists/schrodinger/), [Max Planck](https://www.informationphilosopher.com/solutions/scientists/planck/), and others hoped for a return to deterministic physics, and the elimination of mysterious quantum phenomena like [_superposition of states_](https://www.informationphilosopher.com/solutions/experiments/dirac_three-polarizers/) and ["collapse" of the wave function](https://www.informationphilosopher.com/solutions/experiments/wave-function_collapse/). EPR continues to fascinate [determinist](https://www.informationphilosopher.com/freedom/determinism.html) philosophers of science hoping to prove that [quantum indeterminacy](https://www.informationphilosopher.com/indeterminacy.html) (ontological randomness) does not exist. Beyond the problem of nonlocality, the EPR thought experiment introduced the problem of "[nonseparability](https://www.informationphilosopher.com/problems/nonseparability/)." In his response to the EPR paper, Schrödinger in 1935 told Einstein that his "separability principle" (_Trennungsprinzip_) was simply wrong. Schrödinger's two-particle wave function Ψ12 can not be separated into the product of single-particle wave functions Ψ1 and Ψ2. The two particles _share some properties_. Instantaneous (simultaneous) [knowledge](https://www.informationphilosopher.com/knowledge/) of a distant particle's property (position or momentum or spin) can be gained by measurement of the same property of a local particle that interacted with the distant particle sometime in the past. The 1935 EPR paper was based on an earlier question of Einstein's about two particles fired toward one another with equal and opposite velocities. He imagined them starting at _t0_ some distance apart and approaching one another with equal high velocities. Then for a short time interval from _t1_ to _t1 + Δt_ the particles are in contact with one another. Einstein described this situation to [Léon Rosenfeld](https://www.informationphilosopher.com/solutions/scientists/rosenfeld/) in 1933. Shortly before he left Germany to emigrate to America, Einstein attended a lecture on quantum electrodynamics by Rosenfeld. Keep in mind that Rosenfeld was perhaps the most dogged defender of the [Copenhagen Interpretation](https://www.informationphilosopher.com/quantum/copenhagen/), which maintains that a particle has no properties until it is measured. After the talk, Einstein asked Rosenfeld, “What do you think of this situation?” > Suppose two particles are set in motion towards each other with the same, very large, momentum, and they interact with each other for a very short time when they pass at known positions. Consider now an observer who gets hold of one of the particles, far away from the region of interaction, and measures its momentum: then, from the conditions of the experiment, he will obviously be able to deduce the momentum of the other particle. If, however, he chooses to measure the position of the first particle, he will be able tell where the other particle is. > > > (_Niels Bohr, His Life and Work as seen by His Friends and Colleagues_, 1967, S. Rozental, pp.128-129) We can diagram a simple case of Einstein’s question as follows after the particles have interacted at the center, using _indistinguishable_ electrons rather than generic particles. ![](https://www.informationphilosopher.com/solutions/experiments/EPR/EPR-1.png) Recall that it was Einstein who discovered in 1924 the _identical_ nature, _indistinguishability_, and _interchangeability_ of some quantum particles. He found that identical particles are not _independent_, altering their quantum statistics. Note that it was [David Bohm](https://www.informationphilosopher.com/solutions/scientists/bohm/) in 1952 who proposed Einstein's problem use electrons. Today many if not most accounts of the EPR paradox describe it with electrons. After the particles interact at _t1_, quantum mechanics describes them with a single two-particle wave function Ψ12 that is not the product of _independent_ single-particle wave functions Ψ1 and Ψ2. In the case of electrons, which are indistinguishable interchangeable particles, it is not proper to say electron 1 goes this way and electron 2 that way. (Nevertheless, it is convenient to label the particles, as we do in the illustration.) Einstein then asked Rosenfeld, “How can the final state of the second particle be influenced by a measurement performed on the first after all interaction has ceased between them?” This was the germ of the [EPR paradox](https://www.informationphilosopher.com/solutions/experiments/EPR/), and ultimately the problem of two-particle [entanglement](https://www.informationphilosopher.com/problems/entanglement/). Why does Einstein question Rosenfeld and describe this as an “influence,” suggesting what he will later call a spooky “action-at-a-distance?” It is only paradoxical in the context of Rosenfeld’s [Copenhagen Interpretation](https://www.informationphilosopher.com/quantum/copenhagen/). The second particle is not itself measured and yet we know something about its properties. The Copenhagen Interpretation says we cannot know properties without an explicit measurement. They say some properties _don't even exist_ until after a measurement. Einstein was clearly correct to tell Rosenfeld that at a later time _t2_, a measurement of one particle's position would instantly establish the position of the other particle - _without measuring it_. Einstein obviously was using _conservation of linear momentum_ implicitly to calculate (and know) the position of the second particle. But this not need be "action-at-a-distance." It is more likely simply "knowledge-at-a-distance." Conservation laws are principles that are much deeper than classical mechanical laws or quantum mechanics. They are the consequence of symmetries in the motions. Einstein's particles that have the same, but opposite, momentum move apart like mirror images of one another. Newton's first law of motion says that they will continue their motions unless some interaction disturbs them. No "influence" or action-at-a-distance by one particle on the other is needed for the motion of the particles to remain symmetric mirror images. It is precisely the lack of interactions that maintains the conservation of momentum. Shortly after EPR, Schrödinger described two such particles as becoming "entangled" (_verschränkt_) at their first interaction, so "nonlocal" phenomena are also known as "quantum entanglement." Although _conservation laws_ are rarely cited as the explanation, they are the physical reason that entangled particles _always_ produce correlated results for all properties. If the results were not always correlated, the implied violation of a fundamental conservation law would cause a much bigger controversy than entanglement itself, as puzzling as that is. This idea of something measured in one place "influencing" measurements far away challenged what Einstein thought of as "local reality." It came to be known as "nonlocality." Einstein called it a "_spukhaft Fernwirkung_" or "spooky action at a distance." We prefer to describe this phenomenon as "knowledge at a distance." No action has been performed on the distant particle simply because we learn about its position (or spin). Note that this assumes the distant particle has not been disturbed by an intermediate interaction (_e.g._, decoherence) with the environment after the original entanglement. What Would "Action-At-A-Distance" Require? Where EPR used correlated _positions_ of the two particles, modern examples follow [David Bohm](https://www.informationphilosopher.com/solutions/scientists/bohm/)'s correlated electron _spins_. We can ask how the measurement of one particle could possibly influence" or "act on" its distant companion to cause its position or its spin to become correlated perfectly, should it not already be correlated, as we argue, by the symmetry of conservation principles. No correlations between properties of particles at the "separated" positions would mean that 1) in EPR their positions would not be exactly opposite and equidistant from the initial entanglement position, and 2) in Bohm's version, their spins are not exactly opposite in direction, conserving total spin zero of teh original spherically symmetric singlet state of the molecule. How would action-at-a-distance then work to create correlations? The first particle would have to measure the _actual_ position or spin of the distant particle. Next, the first particle would by mechanical means have to change those distant properties to become correlated with itself. The interaction would have to "do work" on the distant particle and accomplish these steps "instantaneously," that is to say these mechanical operations would have to be achieved at speeds much greater than light speed. There is nothing in classical or quantum mechanics that suggests this kind of remote interaction. There is no conceivable communication or signal that could tell the distant particle how exactly it must change itself. There is no self-action by which the second particle can change its own state when told to do so by the first, upon receiving the information about their differences. Can Particles Have Specific Properties _Determined_ Before They Are Measured? No. But Perfectly Correlated _Indeterministic_ (Random) Properties Can Be Created By The Measurements, As Long As Alice And Bob Measure In Exactly the Same Direction, Preserving The Symmetry In classical mechanics, the second EPR particle always does have the exact position needed to conserve linear momentum. In that case, Einstein was right. For quantum mechanics, however, Heisenberg's [uncertainty principle](https://www.informationphilosopher.com/quantum/uncertainty/) limits the position (and momentum) accuracy. Podolsky and Rosen may have hoped to use EPR to deny the uncertainty principle. Einstein criticized their clumsy attempt. For Bohm's spin measurements, the situation is more complex. It is impossible for the particles before measurement to have known spin in all three possible measurement directions, let alone in the direction (angle) Alice and Bob plan to measure. When spin is known/measured in the x-direction, spin in the y- and z-directions becomes indeterminate. So can the spins be initially entangled in the exact direction that Alice or Bob choose to measure? No/ There are two problems with this assumption of a preferred direction created during the initial entanglement. 1) If Alice and Bob are free to choose their measurement direction, there is little chance they would choose that preferred initial direction. If they measure at an angle θ to that direction, correlations will no longer be perfect, falling off as the cosine of the angle θ, with no correlation at all for θ = 90°. Since Alice and Bob get perfect correlations in any direction, assuming they agree in advance on the direction and both measure in their chosen direction, there appears to be no initial preferred direction. The symmetry before their measurement is preserved by their symmetric measurements in the same direction. 2) The initial entangled state has total spin zero (the so-called _singlet_ state). It is rotationally symmetric, _isotropic_, the same in all directions. If there were an initial preferred direction, that rotational symmetry would be destroyed. If there had been an initial preferred direction, it could not be known to Alice and Bob. We will see how the perfect rotational symmetry of the initial entangled state with total spin zero can provide the explanation for Alice and Bob getting perfect (but random) correlations whatever their choice of measurement angle. Their choice of a measurement direction breaks the _rotational_ symmetry (in all directions) of the initial total spin zero state. But it preserves the _planar_ symmetry (and total spin zero) in their pre-agreed-upon chosen direction, conserving total spin angular momentum. If it did not, a conservation law would have been violated. That cannot be. Conservation is a principle deeper than mere mechanical laws, classical or quantum. We can say that a _joint (shared) property_ of total spin zero existed before (and then after) their measurements. It existed in all directions and at all times. What did not exist before their measurements is the random up-down or down-up result of their measurements. [Erwin Schrödinger](https://www.informationphilosopher.com/solutions/scientist/schrodinger/)'s two-particle wave function describes the two entangled particles as in a linear combination (a [superposition](https://www.informationphilosopher.com/solutions/theories/superposition)) of up-down and down-up states. Their measurement randomly produces one of these states. This is the sense in which observers "create reality" with an experimental measurement. [Niels Bohr](https://www.informationphilosopher.com/solutions/scientists/bohr/) and Werner Heisenberg made the "free choice" as to what to measure a central element of their [Copenhagen Interpretation](https://www.informationphilosopher.com/quantum/copenhagen/). Alice and Bob freely choose the direction in which they measure. But whether their measurement outcomes are up-down or down-up is totally random (indeterministic). [Paul Dirac](https://www.informationphilosopher.com/solutions/scientist/dirac/) called this "Nature's choice," not controllable by the experimenters but caused/created by their measurements. The "free choice" of direction breaks the rotational symmetry of the total spin zero state. But it preserves the planar symmetry defined by Alice and Bob's (pre-agreed upon) measurement direction. This preserves the symmetry needed to conserve angular momentum in the chosen direction. But "Nature's choice" of outcome, whether Alice up-Bob down or Alice down-Bob up, creates the random but perfectly correlated spin properties that the Copenhagen Interpretation correctly says did not exist before the measurement. Our analysis shows these random properties could not have existed at the initial entanglement. They are brought into existence by the experimenters' "free choice." So the conservation of angular momentum alone can explain the perfect correlation of entangled electron spins with no needed faster-than-light interaction "at a distance" between the particles, _as long as Alice and Bob measure in their previously agreed upon chosen direction_. Particles do not have the exact properties needed before the measurements. Quantum theory and the conservation principle predicts that measurements in a pre-agreed-upon direction can create perfectly correlated random properties. And thousands of Bell's theorem test experiments have confirmed that theory, explaining how perfectly correlated random bit strings can be created by Alice and Bob at vastly separated places, without any "spooky action-at-a-distance," just what is needed for quantum cryptography. ## A Hidden Constant? Because the conservation of total spin angular momentum is true from the moment of entanglement state preparation until after the measurements by Alice and Bob at arbitrarily large separations (as long as no external interactions take place), we describe the conserved total spin as providing a "hidden constant of the motion." Physicists from [David Bohm](https://www.informationphilosopher.com/solutions/scientist/bohm/) to [John Bell](https://www.informationphilosopher.com/solutions/scientist/bell/) hoped to find "hidden variables" that could travel with the entangled particles, to ensure that their spins would be found opposite to one another. The principle of conservation of angular momentum together with the experimental fact that spins in Bell test experiments are always found opposite one another gives us confidence that, although the (random) spin directions are unknown, they are opposite in the moment before measurements by Alice and Bob and thus opposite when measured. See our hypothesis of a [Hidden Constant of the Motion](https://www.informationphilosopher.com/quantum/hidden_constant/), all that is necessary to explain entanglement without superluminal "spooky action-at-a-distance." Perhaps "hidden constant" is too cute, although it travels along with the particles just as [David Bohm](https://www.informationphilosopher.com/solutions/scientists/bohm/)'s hidden variables or [David Mermin](https://www.informationphilosopher.com/solutions/scientists/mermin/)'s "instruction sets" do. A more modest name might be a [common cause](https://www.informationphilosopher.com/quantum/common_cause) in the past history of the two particles. ## Disentanglement In the year following the [Einstein-Podsky-Rosen](https://www.informationphilosopher.com/solutions/experiments/EPR/) paper, [Erwin Schrödinger](https://www.informationphilosopher.com/solutions/scientist/schrodinger/) looked more carefully at [Einstein](https://www.informationphilosopher.com/solutions/scientist/einstein/)'s "separability" assumption (_Trennungsprinzip_) that an entangled system can be separated enough to be regarded as two systems with independent wave functions. > Years ago I pointed out that when two systems separate far enough to make it possible to experiment on one of them without interfering with the other, they are bound to pass, during the process of separation, through stages which were beyond the range of quantum mechanics as it stood then. For it seems hard to imagine a complete separation, whilst the systems are still so close to each other, that, from the classical point of view, their interaction could still be described as an unretarded _actio in distans_. And ordinary quantum mechanics, on account of its thoroughly unrelativistic character, really only deals with the _actio in distans_ case. The whole system (comprising in our case both systems) has to be small enough to be able to neglect the time that light takes to travel across the system, compared with such periods of the system as are essentially involved in the changes that take place... > > It seems worth noticing that the paradox could be avoided by a very simple assumption, namely if the situation after separating were described by the expansion > [_ψ (x,y) = Σ ak gk(x) fk(y)_ (as assumed in EPR], > but with the additional statement that the knowledge of the phase relations between the complex constants ak has been entirely lost in consequence of the process of separation. > > When some interaction, like a measurement, causes a _separation_, the two-particle wave function Ψ12 collapses, the system _decoheres_ into the product of single-particle wave functions Ψ1Ψ2. Loss of coherent phase relations means the two particles no longer can interfere, but properties of the second system can still be determined by (nonlocal) measurements on the first (or vice versa). > > This would mean that not only the parts, but the whole system, would be in the situation of a mixture, not of a pure state. It would not preclude the possibility of determining the state of the first system by suitable measurements in the second one or vice versa. But it would utterly eliminate the experimenters influence on the state of that system which he does not touch. > > > ("[Probability Relations between Separated Systems](https://www.informationphilosopher.com/solutions/scientist/schrodinger/Schrodinger-1936.pdf)," _Proceedings of the Cambridge Physical Society_ 1936, 32, issue 2, p.446-452) Schrödinger says that the entangled system may become _disentangled_ (Einstein's separation) and yet some perfect correlations between later measurements might remain. Note that the entangled system could simply [decohere](https://www.informationphilosopher.com/quantum/decoherence/) as a result of interactions with the environment, as proposed by [decoherence](https://www.informationphilosopher.com/quantum/decoherence/) theorists. The perfectly correlated results of [Bell-inequality](https://www.informationphilosopher.com/quantum/bell_theorem/) experiments might nevertheless be preserved, depending on the interaction. Schrödinger tells us that the two-particle wave function Ψ12 will be disentangled into the product of single-particle wave functions Ψ1 and Ψ2 by a measurement of either particle, for example, by either Alice's or Bob's measurements in the case of [Bell's Theorem](https://www.informationphilosopher.com/quantum/bell_theorem/). As we saw, Einstein had objected to nonlocal phenomena as early as the Solvay Conference of 1927, when he criticized the [collapse of the wave function](https://www.informationphilosopher.com/solutions/experiments/wave-function_collapse/) as "instantaneous-action-at-a-distance" that prevents the wave from "acting at more than one place on the screen." The simultaneous events at points A and B in Einstein's 1927 Figure 1 above are the same kind of _nonlocality_ as the two entangled particles acquiring perfectly correlated properties while in a spacelike separation that he suggested to Rosenfeld in 1933, and which Podolsky and Rosen developed into the EPR paradox in 1935. Einstein's 1927 concern was based on the idea that the light wave might contain some kind of ponderable energy. At that time Schrödinger thought it might be distributed electricity. In these cases the instantaneous ["collapse" of the wave function](https://www.informationphilosopher.com/solutions/experiments/wave-function_collapse/) might violate Einstein's principle of relativity, a concern he first expressed in 1909. When we recognize that the wave function is only pure information about the probability of finding a particle (or particles) somewhere, we see that there is no matter or energy (or in particular no information or signal of any kind) traveling faster than the speed of light in the so-called "collapse." Einstein's criticism somewhat resembles the criticisms by Descartes and others about Newton's theory of gravitation. Newton's opponents charged that his theory was "action at a distance" and instantaneous. Einstein's own theory of general relativity shows that gravitational influences travel at the speed of light and are mediated by a gravitational field that can be described as curved space-time. When a probability function collapses to unity in one place and zero elsewhere, nothing physical is moving from one place to the other. When the nose of one horse crosses the finish line, its probability of winning goes to certainty, and the finite probabilities of the other horses, including the one in the rear, instantaneously drop to zero. This happens faster than the speed of light, since the last horse is in a "space-like" separation. But this does not violate relativity. Only abstract "[information](https://www.informationphilosopher.com/introduction/information/)" or "[knowledge](https://www.informationphilosopher.com/problems/entanglement/knowledge)" is changing. The first practical and workable experiments to test the 1935 "thought experiments" of Einstein, Podolsky, and Rosen (EPR) were suggested by [David Bohm](https://www.informationphilosopher.com/solutions/scientists/bohm/) in 1952. Instead of measuring linear momentum, Bohm proposed using two hydrogen atoms that are prepared in an initial state of known total spin angular momentum zero. Momentum and position are _continuous_ variables. Spin is _discrete_. Bohm argued that measurements of discrete variables would be more precise. Bohm also proposed local "hidden variables" might be needed to explain the correlations. Here is Bohm's description > We consider a molecule of total spin zero consisting of two atoms, each of spin one-half. The wave function of the system is therefore > > _ψ_ = (1/√2) [ _ψ+ (1) ψ- (2) - ψ- (1) ψ+ (2)_ ] > > where ψ_+_ (1) refers to the wave function of the atomic state in which one particle (A) has spin +ℏ/2, etc. The two atoms are then separated by a method that does not influence the total spin. After they have separated enough so that they cease to interact, any desired component of the spin of the first particle (A) is measured. Then, because the total spin is still zero, it can immediately be concluded that the same component of the spin of the other particle (B) is opposite to that of A. > > > "Discussion of Experimental Proof for the Paradox of Einstein, Rosen, and Podolsky,” _Physical Review_, vol.108, no.4. p.1070, 1957 Note that when Bohm says "_because the total spin is still zero, it can immediately be concluded that the same component of the spin of the other particle (B) is opposite to that of A,_" he is _implicitly_ using the conservation of total spin. Can you see that our ["hidden" constant of the motion](https://www.informationphilosopher.com/quantum/hidden_constant/) hypothesis is implicit in Bohm's description? In 1964, [John Bell](https://www.informationphilosopher.com/solutions/scientists/bell/) put limits on Bohm's "hidden variables" that might restore a deterministic physics in the form of what he called an _inequality_, the violation of which would confirm standard quantum mechanics. Here is Bell's description. As with Bohm, conservation is not mentioned explicitly, but it involves spin components measured in the same direction at A and B. > With the example advocated by Bohm and Aharonov, the EPR argument is the following. Consider a pair of spin one-half particles formed somehow in the singlet spin state and moving freely in opposite directions. Measurements can be made, say by Stern-Gerlach magnets, on selected components of the spins **σ**1 and **σ**2. If measurement of the component **σ**1 • **a**, where **a** is some unit vector, yields the value + 1 then, according to quantum mechanics, measurement of **σ**2 • **a** must yield the value — 1 and vice versa. Now we make the hypothesis, and it seems one at least worth considering, that if the two measurements are made at places remote from one another the orientation of one magnet does not influence the result obtained with the other.  > > "[pre-determination](https://www.informationphilosopher.com/freedom/pre-determinism.html)" is too strong a term. The first measurement just "determines" the later measurement. We shall see that the second measurement is synchronous with the "first" in a "special" frame > > Since we can predict in advance the result of measuring any chosen component of **σ**2, by previously measuring the same component of **σ**1, it follows that the result of any such measurement must actually be predetermined. > > Since the initial quantum mechanical wave function does not determine the result of an individual measurement, this predetermination implies the possibility of a more complete specification of the state. > > > ("[On the Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen Paradox](https://www.informationphilosopher.com/problems/entanglement/Bell_On_EPR.pdf)," _Physics_, 1.3, p.195.) In his 1980 book, _Wholeness and the Implicate Order_, Bohm emphasized even more strongly that _no interaction between particles is needed_ > Consider a molecule of zero total spin, consisting of two atoms of spin ℏ/2. Let this molecule be disintegrated by a method not influencing the spin of either atom. The total spin then remains zero, even while the atoms are flying apart and have ceased to interact appreciably. > > Now, if any component of the spin of one of the atoms (say A) is measured, then because the total spin is zero, we can immediately conclude that this component of the spin of the other atom (B) is precisely opposite. Thus, by measuring any component of the spin of the atom A, we can obtain this component of the spin of atom B, _without interacting with atom B in any way_... > > > (_Wholeness and the Implicate Order_, pp.71-72. In 2002 edition, pp.91-92) The two spins are correlated and this permits us to know the spin of atom B when we measure that of A. Bohm and Bell are _implicitly_ using the conservation of total spin, supporting our ["hidden constant"](https://www.informationphilosopher.com/quantum/hidden_constant/) hypothesis. If one electron spin is ℏ/2 in the up direction and the other is spin down or -ℏ/2, the total spin is zero. The underlying physical law of importance is not conservation of _linear_ momentum (as Einstein used in EPR). Bohm and Bell use the conservation of _angular momentum (or spin)_. If electron 1 is prepared with spin down and electron 2 with spin up, the total angular momentum is zero. This is called the _singlet_ state. ![](https://www.informationphilosopher.com/solutions/experiments/EPR/EPR-2.png) Bohm and Bell agree that quantum theory describes the two electrons as in a [superposition](https://www.informationphilosopher.com/quantum/principles/) of spin up ( + ) and spin down ( - ) states, | _ψ_ > = 1/√2) | _+_ _-_ > - 1/√2) | _-_ _+_ >         (1) The principles of quantum mechanics say that the prepared system is in a linear combination (or [superposition](https://www.informationphilosopher.com/quantum/principles/)) of these two states, and can provide only the probabilities of finding the entangled system in either the | _+_ _-_ > state or the | _-_ _+_ > state. The 1/√2 coefficients of the probability amplitude for each term, when squared, give us the probabilities (1/2) that the system will be found in the state | _+_ _-_ > or in the state | _-_ _+_ >. The actual outcome is random ([Paul Dirac](https://www.informationphilosopher.com/solutions/scientists/dirac/) called it "Nature's choice." But the individual electron spin outcomes are not _individually and separately_ random, because the particles are not independent. One is always up and the other down, as the conservation law and our ["hidden constant"](https://www.informationphilosopher.com/quantum/hidden_constant/) hypothesis require. Should measurements ever show both spins in the same state, either | _+_ _+_ > or | _-_ _-_ >, that would violate the conservation of angular momentum. Quantum mechanics does not include such terms in the wave function. So they are not predicted and they are never observed, when measurements by Alice and Bob are made in the pre-agreed upon same direction. EPR tests can be done more easily with polarized photons than with electrons, which require a vacuum and complex magnetic fields. The first of these was done in 1972 by Stuart Freedman and [John Clauser](http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/John_Clauser) at UC Berkeley. Their data, in agreement with quantum mechanics, violated the Bell's inequalities to high statistical accuracy, thus providing strong evidence against local hidden-variable theories. If hidden variables exist, they must be non-local, said Bell. For more on _superposition of states_ and the physics of photons, see the [Dirac 3-polarizers experiment](https://www.informationphilosopher.com/solutions/experiments/dirac_3-polarizers/). [John Clauser, Michael Horne, Abner Shimony, and Richard Holt](http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/CHSH_inequality) (known collectively as CHSH) and later [Alain Aspect](http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Alain_Aspect) did more sophisticated tests. The outputs of the polarization analyzers were fed to a coincidence detector that records the instantaneous measurements, described as + -, - +, + +, and - - . The first two ( + - and - + ) conserve the spin angular momentum and are the only types ever observed in these nonlocality/entanglement tests, when measurements are made in the same direction. ![](https://www.informationphilosopher.com/solutions/experiments/EPR/EPR-4.png) With the exception of some of Holt's early results that were found to be erroneous, _no evidence has so far been found of any failure of standard quantum mechanics_. And as experimental accuracy has improved by orders of magnitude, quantum physics has correspondingly been confirmed to one part in 1018, and the transfer speed of the probability information between particles has a lower limit of 106 times the speed of light. There has been no evidence for local "hidden variables." Nevertheless, experimenters continue to look for possible "loopholes" in the experimental results, such as detector inefficiencies that might be hiding results favorable to Einstein's picture of "local reality." [Nicolas Gisin](https://www.informationphilosopher.com/solutions/scientists/gisin/) and his colleagues have extended the polarized photon tests of EPR and the [Bell inequalities](https://www.informationphilosopher.com/solutions/experiments/bells_theorem/) to a separation of 18 kilometers near Geneva. They continue to find 100% correlation and no evidence of the "hidden variables" sought after by Einstein and [David Bohm](https://www.informationphilosopher.com/solutions/scientists/bohm/). ![](https://www.informationphilosopher.com/solutions/experiments/EPR/Putnam_Rietdijk.png) An interesting use of the special theory of relativity was proposed by Gisin's colleagues, [Antoine Suarez](https://www.informationphilosopher.com/solutions/scientists/suarez/) and Valerio Scarani. They use the idea of hyperplanes of simultaneity. Back in the 1960's, [C. W. Rietdijk](https://www.informationphilosopher.com/solutions/philosophers/rietdijk/) and [Hilary Putnam](https://www.informationphilosopher.com/solutions/philosophers/rietdijk/) argued that physical [determinism](https://www.informationphilosopher.com/freedom/determinism.html) could be proved to be true by considering the experiments and observers A and B in the above diagram to be moving at high speed with respect to one another. [Roger Penrose](https://www.informationphilosopher.com/solutions/scientists/penrose/) developed a similar argument in his book _The Emperor's New Mind_. He called it the [Andromeda Paradox](https://www.informationphilosopher.com/solutions/scientists/penrose/#Andromeda_Paradox). Suarez and Scarani showed that for some relative speeds between the two observers A and B, observer A could "see" the measurement of observer B to be in his future, and vice versa. Because the two experiments have a "spacelike" separation (neither is inside the causal light cone of the other), each observer thinks he does his own measurement before the other. Gisin tested the limits on this effect by moving mirrors in the path to the birefringent crystals and showed that, like all other Bell experiments, the "_before-before_" suggestion of Suarez and Scarani did nothing to invalidate quantum mechanics. These experiments were able to put a lower limit on the speed with which the information about probabilities collapses, estimating it as at least thousands - perhaps millions - of times the speed of light and showed empirically that probability collapses are essentially instantaneous. Despite all his experimental tests verifying quantum physics, including the "reality" of nonlocality and entanglement, Gisin continues to explore the EPR paradox, considering the possibility that signals are coming to the entangled particles from "outside space-time." ## How Information Physics Explains Nonlocality, Nonseparability, and Entanglement Information physics starts with the fact that measurements bring new stable and [irreversible](https://www.informationphilosopher.com/problems/reversibility/) [information](https://www.informationphilosopher.com/introduction/information/) into existence. In EPR the information in the prepared state of the two particles includes the fact that the total linear momentum and the total angular momentum are zero. New information requires an irreversible process that also increases the entropy more than enough to compensate for the information increase, to satisfy the second law of thermodynamics. It is this moment of irreversibility and the creation of new _observable_ information that is the "cut" or Schnitt" described by [Werner Heisenberg](https://www.informationphilosopher.com/solutions/scientists/heisenberg/) and [John von Neumann](https://www.informationphilosopher.com/solutions/scientists/neumann/) in the famous [problem of measurement](https://www.informationphilosopher.com/problems/measurement/) Note that the new observable information does not require a "[conscious observer](https://www.informationphilosopher.com/problems/measurement/#conscious_observer)" as [Eugene Wigner](https://www.informationphilosopher.com/solutions/scientists/wigner/) and some other scientists thought. The information is _ontological_ (really in the world) and not merely _epistemic_ (in the mind). Without new information encoded in the world, there would be nothing for the observers to observe. ### Initially Prepared Information Plus Conservation Laws Conservation laws are the consequence of extremely deep properties of nature that arise from simple considerations of symmetry. We regard these laws as "cosmological principles." Physical laws do not depend on the absolute place and time of experiments, nor their particular direction in space. Conservation of linear momentum depends on the translation invariance of physical systems, conservation of energy the independence of time, and conservation of angular momentum the invariance under rotations. Conservation laws are the consequence of symmetries, as explained by [Emmy Noether](https://www.informationphilosopher.com/solutions/scientists/noether/). Recall that the EPR experiment (Bohm version) starts with two electrons (or photons) prepared in an entangled state that is a mixture of pure two-particle states, each of which conserves the total angular momentum and, of course, conserves the linear momentum as in Einstein's original EPR example. This information about the linear and angular momenta is established by the initial state preparation (a measurement). Quantum mechanics describes the probability amplitude wave function _Ψ12_ of the two-particle system as in a _superposition_ of two-particle states. It is _not_ a product of single-particle states, and there is no information about the identical _indistinguishable_ electrons traveling along _distinguishable_ paths. With slightly different notation, we can write equation (1) as _Ψ12_ = 1/√2) | _1+2-_ > + 1/√2) | _1-2+_ >         (2) The probability amplitude wave function _Ψ12_ travels away from the source (at the speed of light or less). Let's assume that at _t0_ observer A finds an electron (e1) with spin up. At the time of this "first" measurement, by observer A or B, new information comes into existence telling us that the wave function _Ψ12_ has "collapsed" into the state | _1+2-_ > (or into | _1-2+_ >). Just as in the [two-slit experiment](https://www.informationphilosopher.com/solutions/experiments/two-slit_experiment/), probabilities have now become certainties, one possibility is now an actuality. If the first measurement finds a particular component of electron 1 spin is up, so the same spin component of entangled electron 2 must be down to conserve angular momentum. And conservation of linear momentum tells us that at _t0_ the second electron is equidistant from the source in the opposite direction. ![](https://www.informationphilosopher.com/solutions/experiments/EPR/EPR-asymmetric.gif) As with any [wave-function "collapse"](https://www.informationphilosopher.com/solutions/experiments/wave-function_collapse/), the probability amplitude information changes (it does not "travel" anywhere). Nothing really "collapses." Nothing is moving. Only information is changing. Unlike the [two-slit experiment](https://www.informationphilosopher.com/solutions/experiments/two-slit_experiment/), where the "collapse" goes to a specific point in 3-dimensional configuration space, the "collapse" here is a "jump" (Bohr) or a "projection" (Dirac) or a "reduction" (Heisenberg) into one of the two possible 6-dimensional two-particle quantum states | _+_ _-_ > or | _-_ _+_ >. This makes "visualization" (Schrödinger's _Anschaulichkeit_) difficult or impossible, but the parallel with the collapse in the two-slit case provides an intuitive insight of sorts. In both cases, the values of the probability wave function changes instantly over a wide range of space. This is what Einstein saw in 1905 with the light wave spread out everywhere collapsing into a photon, in 1927 with the probability of a particle being found everywhere on a spherical surface collapses to the spot where it is found, and again in 1933 where observing a particle in one place tells us exactly where the other one is far away. If the measurement finds an electron (call it electron 1) as spin-up, then at that moment of new information creation, the two-particle wave function collapses to the state | _+_ _-_ > and electron 2 "jumps" into a spin-down state with probability unity (certainty). The results of observer B's measurement at a later time _t1_ is therefore _determined_ to be spin down. Notice that [Einstein](https://www.informationphilosopher.com/solutions/scientists/einstein/)'s intuition that the result seems already "determined" or "fixed" before the second measurement is in fact correct. The result is determined by the law of conservation of momentum. But as with the distinction between [determinism](https://www.informationphilosopher.com/freedom/determinism.html) and [_pre_-determinism](https://www.informationphilosopher.com/freedom/pre-determinism.html) in the [free-will](https://www.informationphilosopher.com/freedom/free-will.html) debates, the measurement by observer B was not pre-determined _before_ observer A's measurement. It was simply _determined by_ her measurement. ### Why do so few accounts of entanglement mention conservation laws? Although Einstein mentioned conservation in the original EPR paper, it is noticeably absent from later work. Bohm and Bell are obviously using it without an explicit mention. A prominent exception is [Eugene Wigner](https://www.informationphilosopher.com/solutions/scientists/wigner/), writing on the [problem of measurement](https://www.informationphilosopher.com/problems/measurement/) in 1963: > If a measurement of the momentum of one of the particles is carried out — the possibility of this is never questioned — and gives the result **p**, the state vector of the other particle suddenly becomes a (slightly damped) plane wave with the momentum -**p**. This statement is synonymous with the statement that a measurement of the momentum of the second particle would give the result -**p**, as follows from the conservation law for linear momentum. The same conclusion can be arrived at also by a formal calculation of the possible results of a joint measurement of the momenta of the two particles. > > Writing a few years after Bohm, and one year before Bell, Wigner explicitly describes Einstein's conservation of _linear_ momentum in EPR as well as the conservation of angular momentum (spin) that explains perfect correlations between angular momentum (spin) components if (and only if) measured in the same direction > > One can go even further: instead of measuring the linear momentum of one particle, one can measure its angular momentum about a fixed axis. If this measurement yields the value _mℏ_, the state vector of the other particle suddenly becomes a cylindrical wave for which the same component of the angular momentum is -_mℏ_. This statement is again synonymous with the statement that a measurement of the said component of the angular momentum of the second particle certainly would give the value -_mℏ_. This can be inferred again from the conservation law of the angular momentum (which is zero for the two particles together) or by means of a formal analysis. > > (_The Problem of Measurement_, Eugene Wigner, in Wheeler and Zurek, _Quantum Theory and Measurement_, p,340) ## Visualizing Entanglement and Nonlocality [Schrödinger](https://www.informationphilosopher.com/solutions/scientists/schrodinger/) said that his "Wave Mechanics" provided more "visualizability" (_Anschaulichkeit_) than the Copenhagen school and its "damned quantum jumps" as he called them. He was right. But we must focus on the probability amplitude wave function of the prepared two-particle state, and not attempt to describe the paths or locations of independent particles - at least until _after_ some measurement has been made. We must also keep in mind the conservation laws that Einstein used to discover nonlocal behavior in the first place. Then we can see that the "[mystery](https://www.informationphilosopher.com/freedom/mysteries.html)" of nonlocality is primarily the same mystery as the single-particle [collapse of the wave function](https://www.informationphilosopher.com/solutions/experiments/wave-function_collapse/). As [Richard Feynman](https://www.informationphilosopher.com/solutions/scientists/feynman/) said, there is _only one mystery_ in quantum mechanics (the collapse of probability and the consequent statistical outcomes). > We choose to examine a phenomenon which is impossible, _absolutely_ impossible, to explain in any classical way, and which has in it the heart of quantum mechanics. In reality, it contains the _only_ mystery. We cannot make the mystery go away by "explaining" how it works. We will just _tell_ you how it works. In telling you how it works we will have told you about the basic peculiarities of all quantum mechanics. > > (_The Feynman Lectures on Physics_, vol III, 1-1) In his 1935 paper, Schrödinger described the two particles in EPR as "entangled" in English, and _verschränkt_ in German, which means something like cross-linked. It describes someone standing with arms crossed. In the time evolution of an entangled two-particle state according to the Schrödinger equation, we can visualize it - as we visualize the single-particle wave function - as collapsing when a measurement is made. The discontinuous "jump" is also described as the "reduction of the wave packet." This is apt in the two-particle case, where the superposition of | + - > and | - + > states is "projected" or "reduced: to one of these states, and then further reduced to the product of independent one-particle states | + > and | - >. In the two-particle case (instead of just one particle making an appearance), when either particle is measured we know instantly those properties of the other particle that satisfy the conservation laws, including its location equidistant from, but on the opposite side of, the source, and its other properties such as spin. Here is an animation showing the two particles simultaneously acquiring their opposite spins when either is measured. ![](https://www.informationphilosopher.com/solutions/experiments/EPR/EPR-collapse.gif) ### How Mysterious Is Entanglement? Some commentators say that nonlocality and entanglement are a "second revolution" in quantum mechanics, "the greatest mystery in physics," or "science's strangest phenomenon," and that quantum physics has been "reborn." They usually quote Erwin Schrödinger as saying > "I consider [entanglement] not as one, but as _the_ characteristic trait of quantum mechanics, the one that enforces its entire departure from classical lines of thought." Schrödinger knew that his two-particle wave function Ψ12 cannot have the same simple interpretation as the single particle, which can be visualized in ordinary 3-dimensional configuration space. And he is right that entanglement exhibits a richer form of the "action-at-a-distance" and nonlocality that Einstein had already identified in the ["collapse" of the single particle wave function](https://www.informationphilosopher.com/solutions/experiments/wave-function_collapse/). But the main difference is that on measurement _two_ particles acquire new properties instead of one particle, and they do it instantaneously (simultaneously), just as the single-particle wave function changes instantly over large volumes in the case of a single-particle measurement. Nonlocality and entanglement are thus another manifestation of [Richard Feynman](https://www.informationphilosopher.com/solutions/scientists/feynman/)'s "_only_" mystery in the two-slit experiment. ## Is There an Asymmetry Here? Here we must explain the _asymmetry_ that Einstein and Schrödinger have introduced into a perfectly symmetric situation, making entanglement such a mystery. Every follower of their early thinking introduces this [false asymmetry](https://www.informationphilosopher.com/problems/entanglement/asymmetry/). The classic EPR idea is completely symmetric about the origin of the state preparation. Einstein introduced the mistaken idea of measuring one particle "first" and then asking how it influences _subsequent_ measurements of the "second" particle. By contrast, Schrödinger's two-particle wave function "collapses" at all positions in an instant of time. Both particles then appear in a space-like separation. The perfectly symmetric picture shows that neither Alice nor Bob can in any way influence the other's experiment, as can be seen best in what we can call a _special frame_. There is a special frame in which the collapse of the two-particle wave function is best visualized. It is not a _preferred frame_ in the special relativistic sense (e.g., an inertial frame). But observers in all other frames in relative motion along the experiment axis will see one of the measurements before the other. Relativity contributes confusion to what is going on. Almost every presentation of the EPR paradox begins with something like "Alice observes one particle..." and concludes with the question "How does the second particle get the information needed so that Bob's measurements _correlate_ perfectly with Alice?" There is a fundamental asymmetry in this framing of the EPR experiment. It is a surprise that Einstein, who was so good at seeing deep symmetries, did not consider how to remove the asymmetry. Even more puzzling, why did he introduce it? Why do most all subsequent scientists accept it without question? Consider this reframing: Alice's measurement collapses the two-particle wave function. The two indistinguishable particles simultaneously appear at locations in a space-like separation. The frame of reference in which the source of the two entangled particles and the two experimenters are at rest is a special frame in the following sense. As Einstein knew very well, there are frames of reference moving with respect to the laboratory frame of the two observers in which the time order of the events can be reversed. In some moving frames Alice measures first, but in others Bob measures first. If there is a special frame of reference (not a _preferred frame_ in the relativistic sense), surely it is the one in which the origin of the two entangled particles is at rest. Assuming that Alice and Bob are also at rest in this special frame and equidistant from the origin, we arrive at the simple picture in which any measurement that causes the two-particle wave function to collapse makes both particles appear simultaneously at determinate places with fully correlated properties (just those that are needed to conserve energy, momentum, angular momentum, and spin). ![](https://www.informationphilosopher.com/images/preferred_animation.gif) In the two-particle case (instead of just one particle making an appearance), when either particle is measured, we know instantly those properties of the other particle that satisfy the conservation laws, including its location equidistant from, but on the opposite side of, the entangling interaction, and all other properties such as spin. It's just "_knowledge-at-a-distance_." ## No "Hidden Variables," But Perhaps A "Hidden Constant?" Although we find no need for "hidden variables," whether local or non-local, we might say that the conservation laws give us a "hidden constant." Conservation of a particular property is often described as a "constant of the motion." Such a constant might be viewed as "local," in that it travels along with the particles as a shared property, true at all times, or as "global," in that it is a property of the two-particle probability amplitude wave function Ψ12 as it spreads out in space. This agrees with Bohm, and especially with Bell, who says that if the spin of particle 1 is measured to be up, then particle 2 is "predetermined" to be found to be down (if, and only if, the two particles are measured in the same direction). But recall that the [Copenhagen Interpretation](https://www.informationphilosopher.com/quantum/copenhagen/) says _we cannot know_ a spin property until it is measured. So some claim that both spins are in an unknown value of spin or and spin up until the measurements. It is this that suggests the possibility that both spins might be found in the same direction, both up or both down, which would violate the conservation laws. Since electron spins in this situation are never found experimentally in the same direction, this gave rise to the idea of a hidden variable as some sort of signal that could travel to particle 2 after the measurement of particle 1, causing it to change its spin to be opposite that of particle 1. What sort of signal might this be? And what mechanism exists in a bare electron that could cause it to change a property like its spin without an external force of some kind? Clearly, Wigner's explicit view that a conservation law is operating, and the implicit claims of Bohm and Bell that the electron spins were created in opposite states, are the simplest and clearest explanations of the entanglement mystery. Despite accepting that a particular value of some "observables" can only be known by a measurement ([knowledge](https://www.informationphilosopher.com/knowledge) is an _epistemological_ problem) Einstein asked whether the particle actually (really, ontologically) paths and positions, even other properties, before we measure this? His answer was yes. Einstein might have thought that the two particles have had their spins [predetermined](https://www.informationphilosopher.com/freedom/pre-determinism.html) from the time of their entangling interaction. But as we have shown, the perfectly correlated properties were not created at the initial entanglement preparation but at the measurements by Alice and Bob, who freely chose an agreed upon direction to measure. What must pre-exist is the _jointly shared property_ of conserved total spin angular momentum zero _in all directions_, a symmetry property of the initial entanglement of the two particles, so that whatever direction is freely chosen, the result will be opposite spins to maintain total spin zero, either + -, or - +. Note that if Alice and Bob were to measure at angles differing by an angle θ, the perfect correlations would be reduced by cos2θ. That would introduce measurements of + + and - -, which violate the conservation of total spin zero, proportional to sin2θ. ## Why [Pre-Determination](https://www.informationphilosopher.com/freedom/pre-determinismn.html) Is Not Possible At Initial State Preparation The simple and intuitive idea that the two particles acquired their specific opposite spins when they were prepared, at the moment of entanglement interaction above is unfortunately wrong. Quantum theory tells us that the spins of both particles are undetermined in all directions. Here is a crude animation illustrating the assumption that the two electrons are prepared, one in a spin-up, the other in a spin-down state. They remain in opposite states no matter how far they separate, provided neither interacts with anything else until the measurements at A and B. Two "hidden constants" of the motion, one spin up, one down, might explain the fact of perfect correlations of opposing spins. That "Nature's" initial choice of up-down versus down-up is quantum random explains why the bit strings can be used in quantum encryption. What Schrödinger told us in 1935 is that neither particle has a definite spin direction until a measurement is made of either particle. Schrödinger described the situation before measurement as in a linear combination (a [superposition](https://www.informationphilosopher.com/quantum/superposition/)) of particle 1 spin up, particle 2 spin down and particle 1 spin down, particle 2 spin up. The proper quantum description is that the two-particle wave function is in a linear combination of up-down and down-up states. _Ψ12_ = 1/√2) | _1+2-_ > + 1/√2) | _1-2+_ > Just one of these two _possible_ up-down (+ -) and down-up (- +) states can become _actual_ when measured. The 1/√2 coefficient, when squared, tells us that the two states have probability 1/2. The spin directions and spin values (perfectly correlated) for Alice and Bob do not appear until one of them makes a measurement. And only then if Alice and Bob both measure in the same, previously agreed upon, direction, as [we will visualize below](https://www.informationphilosopher.com/problems/entanglement/#3Dvisual). Note that while individual spin values and directions of the two particles are indeterministic before measurement, the joint or _shared_ property of total spin zero is not indeterministic. While there is no information in this equation about the individual particle spins, the equation contains the certain information that if one particle is measured spin-down, the other must be found spin-up Because the two-particle wave function Ψ12 has total spin zero, as Schrödinger showed, when they are disentangled and become the product of two single-particle wave functions Ψ1 and Ψ2, whichever of the two possible products of single-particle wave functions appears, up-down (+ -) or down-up (- +), both will continue to conserve total spin! If Ψ1 is measured with spin up, then Ψ2 must have spin down in the exact opposite direction, conserving total spin (angular momentum). This lets us know that Ψ2 is spin down without measuring it. We believe that this should be called "knowledge-at-a-distance." There is no superluminal signaling, no physical influence, no "action-at-a-distance." We describe this situation as a single "hidden constant" of the motion. The hidden constant is the total spin zero, a _shared_ property of the two-particle wave function Ψ12. Spin is a constant because of the principle of conservation of angular momentum, based on the rotational symmetry of the two-particle wave function. And this "hidden" constant achieves everything the David Bohm and John Bell hoped their "hidden variables" could do! ## The "Free Choice" of the Experimenter We can establish the fact that there is _no preferred spatial direction_ for the rotationally symmetric two-particle entangled wave function. The founders of quantum mechanics, especially [Werner Heisenberg](https://www.informationphilosopher.com/solutions/scientists/heisenberg/), insists that the experimenter has a "free choice" as to which direction (or component of spin) to measure. It is therefore Alice's "free choice" that introduces the preferred direction into the problem. And it is only measurements by Bob in that same (or opposite) direction that will yield the perfectly correlated (or anti-correlated) values needed for quantum encryption. This preferred direction did not exist before Alice's measurement. And note that although Alice can choose the direction, she cannot choose the outcome, spin up or spin down. As [Paul Dirac](https://www.informationphilosopher.com/solutions/scientists/dirac/) showed, the outcome is [indeterministic](https://www.informationphilosopher.com/freedom/indeterminism.html), a matter of [chance](https://www.informationphilosopher.com/freedom/chance) that he called "Nature's Choice." There is no interaction or action-at-a-distance from Alice to Bob. When the two-particle Ψ12 collapses into disentangled Ψ1 and Ψ2, the new single-particle wave functions have opposite spins in the direction Alice chose to measure. ## Here is a crude two-dimensional animation of this picture, If you move the timeline playhead slowly you can see the two spins are oscillating back and forth, always keeping the total spin zero. [Richard Feynman](https://www.informationphilosopher.com/solutions/scientists/feynman/) described them as arrows spinning randomly in all directions, but none of these visualizations do justice to the underlying fact that there is no preferred direction for the rotationally symmetric total spin zero state of the entangled Ψ12 wave function. ## Principle Theories and Constructivist Theories In his 1933 essay, "On the Method of Theoretical Physics," Albert Einstein argued that the greatest physical theories would be built on "principles," not on constructions derived from physical experience. His theory of special relativity was based on the principle of relativity, that the laws of physics are the same in all inertial frames, along with the constant velocity of light in all frames. Our explanation of entanglement as the result of "hidden constants" of the motion is based on conservation laws, which, as [Emmy Noether](https://www.informationphilosopher.com/solutions/scientists/noether/) showed, are based on still deeper principles of _symmetry_. This "principle" explanation is, of course, also based solidly on the empirical fact that electron spins are always experimentally (constructively) found in opposite directions. ## Summary Explanation of Quantum Entanglement As Einstein should have seen in his discussion with Leon Rosenfeld, the conservation of total zero momentum of identical particles separating with equal but opposite velocities does not depend on any interaction between the particles. Neither particle is "influencing" the motion of the other one to keep their momenta perfectly opposite. They each conserve their own momentum. The case is similar with two quantum particles, whether electrons, photons, atoms, or "buckyballs. " The two-particle wave function Ψ12 describes the probability of finding the two particles somewhere if a measurement is made. As with any quantum wave function, particles can be found anywhere the squared modulus |Ψ2| is not zero. Just as we can say nothing about where a single particle is located before measurement, so we cannot know where the two particles will be found when observed. But we can know that their relative spin directions will always be found to be exactly opposite one another, just as with Einstein's two particles with opposite linear momentum. The perfect rotational symmetry of the two-particle wave function Ψ12 ensures that every direction angle is equally probable. As [Werner Heisenberg](https://www.informationphilosopher.com/solutions/scientists/heisenberg/) and [Pascual Jordan](https://www.informationphilosopher.com/solutions/scientists/Jordan/) liked to describe it, the specific properties of particles are "created" by the measurement, when one of the [possible](https://www.informationphilosopher.com/freedom/possibilities.html) locations and angle directions becomes [actual](https://www.informationphilosopher.com/freedom/actualism.html). Alice's "free choice" of direction to measure ensures that the spin will be found along that angle direction, but randomly up or down in that direction, according to [Paul Dirac](https://www.informationphilosopher.com/solutions/scientists/dirac/)'s idea that this is "Nature's choice." As long as Bob measures at the same pre-agreed angle, he will always find his spin opposite to the direction that Alice found, establishing the perfect anti-correlation of bits needed for quantum encryption. The proper quantum description is that the two-particle wave function is in a linear combination of up-down and down-up states. _Ψ12_ = 1/√2) | _1+2-_ > + 1/√2) | _1-2+_ > Either of these _possible_ states can become _actual_ when measured. Both will conserve spin angular momentum, our "hidden constant of the motion." We might attempt a rough visualization ([Schrödinger](https://www.informationphilosopher.com/solutions/scientists/schrodinger/)'s _Anschaulichkeit_) of the spins of the entangled particles. It is something like an ice-skating couple holding hands while they rotate around one another. But the analogy Is weak, because quantum spins are not in ordinary 3-dimensional space. Below is a 3D visualization that demonstrates the _rotational symmetry_ of two entangled atoms about their molecular axis, for example the hydrogen molecule made up of two hydrogen atoms. You can rotate the molecule to view it from a point on the molecular axis that is outside the molecule. [molecule](https://sketchfab.com/Eliam113/collections/molecule-701416332d8f425b876a01832b9930d3) by [Eliam113](https://sketchfab.com/Eliam113) on [Sketchfab](https://sketchfab.com/?utm_source=website&utm_medium=embed&utm_campaign=share-popup) Click on the play icon and rotate the H2 molecule in any direction. The ground state of the H2 molecule is a 1s2 1Σ+g singlet state with total spin angular momentum zero because the spins of the two electrons are always found in opposite directions. ![](https://www.informationphilosopher.com/problems/entanglement/H2_MO.jpeg) The H2 molecule is almost spherically symmetric, distorted slightly from the homologous covalent 1sσ2 state of the helium atom (which is perfectly spherical) by splitting the He atom into two positive nuclei and separating them to the internuclear distance of the molecule. The ground state being a Σ state, it must have rotational symmetry about the nuclear axis. It is also symmetrical in the two electrons and in the nuclei. In [David Bohm](https://www.informationphilosopher.com/solutions/scientists/bohm/)'s version of EPR he wrote > We consider a molecule of total spin zero consisting of two atoms, each of spin one-half... > > The two atoms are then separated by a method that does not influence the total spin. After they have separated enough so that they cease to interact, any desired component of the spin of the first particle (A) is measured. Then, _because the total spin is still zero_, it can immediately be concluded that the same component of the spin of the other particle (B) is opposite to that of A. > > > "Discussion of Experimental Proof for the Paradox of Einstein, Rosen, and Podolsky,” _Physical Review_, vol.108, no.4. p.1070, 1957 But the measurements by Alice and Bob must be made in the same direction (at the same pre-agreed upon angle) to preserve the symmetry and get that perfectly opposite outcome. We can visualize the positions of their Stern-Gerlach devices located on the extension of the molecule's internuclear axis. If you rotate the animation until you are looking along the internuclear axis, it looks like a perfect circle. In this position you see the rotational symmetry about that axis. If Alice measures "first" at angle α and Bob then measures at a different angle β, since Bohm tells us Bob's particle must be found oriented perfectly opposite at -α, Bob's measurements will be _decorrelated_ by cos(β-α)2. Note that the rotational symmetry about the internuclear axis means that this result happens whichever angle Alice starts with. In experimental terms, the fact that the results don't depend on Alice's choice of angle together with the observed cos(β-α)2 decorrelation seen in all the Bell experiments proves (confirms) that the two-particle wave function is symmetric about the inter-particle axis. which is the flight path of the separating particles. If Bob measures at a different angle from Alice, this destroys the rotational symmetry. As Bohm warned, this would influence the total spin of the two particles, which would no longer be zero. But that would not violate conservation of angular momentum, because the spin of the two Stern-Gerlach devices would also be changed, exactly conserving the combined total angular momentum of the particles and the measurement devices. ### Response to Criticisms of Our Explanation of Quantum Entanglement Critics say that we mistakenly assume that the entangled particles acquire their (perfectly correlated) properties (spin values, positions) _before_ Alice's or Bob's measurement. We don't. We agree their _individual_ properties are indeterministic. But we insist that their _shared_ property of total spin zero (our "hidden constant") is determined by their initial entanglement. The [Copenhagen Interpretation](https://www.informationphilosopher.com/quantum/copenhagen/) and many others agree that quantum properties (spin, position, momentum) normally _do not exist_ before their measurement. (Exceptions are cases of a "state preparation" where a system is put into a definite state. A subsequent measurement finds it in the same state - [Pauli measurements of the first kind](https://www.informationphilosopher.com/solutions/scientists/).) The initial entanglement is such a state preparation. Properties acquired during a measurement are cases in which we say that the observer "creates reality." And we agree that Alice's measurement of spin-up or spin-down in some direction did not exist before her measurement. It was truly random. Dirac calls it Nature's choice". But note that her choice of measurement direction (angle) was her own (Heisenberg's "free choice"). Alice is creating the reality of the spin in her chosen direction. Bob will only get a perfectly correlated (or anti-correlated) result if he measures at exactly the same angle (by pre-agreement with Alice). Only in this case can Alice and Bob generate the correlated sequences of random bits needed for quantum cryptography. So we agree with our critics who say the specific properties created by Alice and Bob (spin and direction angle) do not pre-exist their measurements. However, the critics are also correct that our explanation does require _something to exist before the measurements_. But what pre-exists is not _individual particle properties_. It is instead the _shared_ or _joint_ property of total spin angular momentum zero that the entangled particles acquired when they were initially entangled, and which they carry with them as they travel. We describe this shared property as a "hidden constant of the motion" because it functions just like the "hidden variables" that [David Bohm](https://www.informationphilosopher.com/solutions/scientists/bohm/) and [John Bell](https://www.informationphilosopher.com/solutions/scientists/bell/) hoped for. We believe this "hidden constant" fully explains the [non-local](https://www.informationphilosopher.com/problems/nonlocality/) behavior of entangled particles and the **apparent** violation of relativity. The "hidden constant" for entangled particles is the _total spin zero_ state the particles are in. Without any external interaction (or [_decoherence_](https://www.informationphilosopher.com/quantum/decoherence/) by the environment), the total spin remains zero at all times by the _law of conservation of angular momentum_. Critics are correct that we do not know (_epistemology_) and the particles do not have (_ontology_) specific spin directions or positions. But we do know, and the particles do have, the joint or shared property of total spin zero at all times. (The two-particle wave function Ψ12 is _rotationally symmetric_, a symmetry that underlies the conservation of angular momentum, according to [Emmy Noether](https://www.informationphilosopher.com/solutions/scientists/noether/).) Specifically, conservation of momentum laws mean that just before the measurement, whatever the unknown spins and positions of the entangled particles, their spins are always exactly opposite to one another, and whatever the unknown positions of the particles, they are equidistant from and on opposite sides of the initial entanglement, as Einstein described to Leon Rosenfeld in 1933 and the 1935 [EPR](https://www.informationphilosopher.com/solutions/experiments/EPR/) authors called "elements of reality" and a "paradox." Again, although we do not know those spins and directions, because they are ontologically indeterminate, the fact that at the instant of Alice's measurement Bob's particle must have exactly opposite properties is not because an "influence" travels from Alice to Bob faster than the speed of light (Einstein's "spooky action at a distance"). It is because the particles must have opposite momenta when measured because the total momentum is prepared to be zero and remains zero at all times up to and including their measurements. If without any external interaction the conservation of angular momentum law were violated at some moment, it would be a much greater problem for physics than entanglement itself, however mysterious and puzzling entanglement may seem. We are surprised that Einstein did not notice this fact. When Bohr, Kramers, and Slater suggested in 1924 that the conservation laws might only be statistically conserved, Einstein immediately suggested the experiment (to Hans Geiger) that would disprove the BKS hypothesis and confirm the conservation principles that are fundamental to both classical physics and quantum physics. ## References [The Ground State of the Hydrogen Molecule](https://home.uni-leipzig.de/pwm/teaching/ep5_ws1213/literature/James_Coolidge_1933_ground_state_hydrogen_molecule.pdf), _Journal of Chemical Physics_, 1933, vol. 1, p.825. [Erwin Schrödinger, Discussion of Probability between Separated Systems (Entanglement Paper)](https://www.informationphilosopher.com/solutions/scientists/schrodinger/Schrodinger-1935.pdf), _Proceedings of the Cambridge Physical Society_ 1935, 31, issue 4, pp.555-563 [David Bohm, A Suggested Interpretation of the Quantum Theory in Terms of "Hidden" Variables. I](https://www.informationphilosopher.com/solutions/scientists/bohm/Hidden_Variables_I) [David Bohm, A Suggested Interpretation of the Quantum Theory in Terms of "Hidden" Variables. II](https://www.informationphilosopher.com/solutions/scientists/bohm/Hidden_Variables_II) [David Bohm and Yakir Aharonov, Discussion of Experimental Proof for the Paradox of Einstein, Rosen, and Podolsky](https://www.informationphilosopher.com/solutions/scientists/bohm/Bohm_Aharonov-.pdf) [John Bell, On the Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen Paradox](https://www.informationphilosopher.com/solutions/scientists/bell/Bell_On_EPR.pdf) "[Albert Einstein, On the Method of Theoretical Physics](https://www.informationphilosopher.com/solutions/scientists/einstein/Method_of_Theoretical_Physics.pdf)," The Herbert Spencer Lecture, Oxford, June 10, 1933, _Ideas and Opinions_, Bonanza Books, 1954, pp.270-276; original German in _Mein Weltbild_, Amsterdam, 1934, (PDF)